Jump to content

Draft:Original research/Lamarckism

From Wikiversity
This is an artist's portrait of Jean-Baptiste Lamarck. Credit: Valérie75.

Lamarckism (or Lamarckian inheritance) is the idea that an organism can pass on characteristics that it acquired during its lifetime to its offspring (also known as heritability of acquired characteristics or soft inheritance). It is named after the French biologist Jean-Baptiste Lamarck (1744–1829), who incorporated the action of soft inheritance into his evolutionary theories.

After Erasmus Darwin wrote Zoonomia suggesting "that all warm-blooded animals have arisen ... with the power of acquiring new parts" in response to stimuli, with each round of "improvements" being inherited by successive generations", Jean-Baptiste Lamarck repeated in his Philosophie Zoologique of 1809 the folk wisdom that characteristics which were "needed" were acquired (or diminished) during the lifetime of an organism then passed on to the offspring.

Neo-Lamarckism is a theory of inheritance based on a modification and extension of Lamarckism, essentially maintaining the principle that genetic changes can be influenced and directed by environmental factors.

Theory of Lamarckism

[edit | edit source]

Def. "[t]he theory that structural variations, characteristic of species and genera, are produced in animals and plants by the direct influence of physical environments, and especially, in the case of animals, by effort, or by use or disuse of certain organs"[1] is called Lamarckism.

Lamarck incorporated two ideas into his theory of evolution, in his day considered to be generally true:

  1. Use and disuse – Individuals lose characteristics they do not require (or use) and develop characteristics that are useful.
  2. Inheritance of acquired traits – Individuals inherit the traits of their ancestors.

Laimology

[edit | edit source]
The evolution of necks is often used as the example in explanations of Lamarckism. Credit: Peter Halasz (Pengo).

Examples of what is traditionally called "Lamarckism" would include:

  • Giraffes stretching their necks to reach leaves high in trees (especially Acacias), strengthen and gradually lengthen their necks. These giraffes have offspring with slightly longer necks (also known as "soft inheritance").
  • A blacksmith, through his work, strengthens the muscles in his arms. His sons will have similar muscular development when they mature.

"The giraffe's neck supposedly supplies a crucial example for preferring natural selection over Lamarckism as a cause of evolution. But Darwin himself (however wrongly by later judgement) did not deny the Lamarckian principle of inheritance for characters acquired by use or lost by disuse. He regarded the Lamarckian mechanism as weak, infrequent, and entirely subsidiary to natural selection, but he accepted the validity of evolution by use and disuse. Darwin does speculate about the adaptive advantage of giraffe's necks, but he cites both natural selection and Lamarckism as probable causes of elongation."[2]

"Henry Fairfield Osborn, the dominant paleontologist of his era, and long time director of the American Museum of Natural History, gave the "standard version in his popular book of 1918, The Origin and Evolution of Life... "Lamarck attributed the lengthening of the [giraffe's] neck to the inheritance of bodily modifications caused by the neck-stretching habit. Darwin attributed the lengthening of the neck to the constant selection of individuals and races which were born with the longest necks. Darwin was probably right." ...The version has held ever since."[2]

Epigenetics

[edit | edit source]

Interest in Lamarckism has recently increased, as several studies in the field of epigenetics have highlighted the possible inheritance of behavioral traits acquired by the previous generation.

"First, there is no reason to think that epigenetic variations are rare: when actively sought, they have usually been found. Second, epigenetic variations can be transmitted very stably, certainly in cell lines. ... Third, epigenetic inheritance is not limited to multicellular organisms: it is found in unicellular organisms too. ... Fourth, several different models have shown how, in certain conditions, transmitting some (not all) epigenetic variations from one generation to the next is a selective advantage, even if they are stable for only a few generations. ... Fifth, epigenetic variations may influence the site and nature of genetic changes and affect evolution in this way. ... [T]here is a Lamarckian component in evolution, with the environment being an inducer as well as a selector of variation."[3]

Hypertrophy

[edit | edit source]

"The inheritance of acquired traits, also known as his 'Second Law' in Philosophie Zoologique, is the idea that the traits of an organism that undergo hypertrophy will be inherited by the next generation. This hypertrophy suggests an adaptation to the environment that can be passed on to the next generation through the genetic code of the organism."[4]

"The Lamarckian view of evolution is seen as a tendency for a species to reach perfection where it is actually simply adapting to their environment in a single generation."[4]

Transmissions

[edit | edit source]

"The development of organs and their power of action are continually determined by the use of these organs." This is known as his [Lamarck's] third law. In the fourth he insisted on the hereditary nature of the effects of such use. "All that has been acquired, begun or changed," he said, "in the course of their life is preserved in reproduction and transmitted to the new individuals which spring from those which have experienced the changes."[5]

Extinctions

[edit | edit source]

"Lamarck did not believe that a species could become extinct. Instead, he saw the idea of extinction as every member of a species evolving into another species. He believed that change was brought about through use and disuse and inheritance of acquired characteristics. This was the first time that a mechanism was proposed in order to explain how a change in a species occurred."[4]

Mutations

[edit | edit source]

"Lamarck was a believer in immutability."[4]

Lysenkoism

[edit | edit source]

"The Lamarckism presented in standard textbooks is actually Lysenkoism, a straw man set up by the opponents of Lamarckism, palpably false and easily disproved."[6]

Lysenko did not apply actual science. He was a proponent of the ideas of Ivan Vladimirovich Michurin, and practiced a form of Lamarckism, insisting on the change in species among plants through hybridization and grafting, as well as a variety of other non-genetic techniques. With this came, most importantly, the implication that acquired characteristics of an organism — for example, the state of being leafless as a result of having been plucked — could be inherited by that organism's descendants.

Orthogenesis

[edit | edit source]

Orthogenesis, orthogenetic evolution, progressive evolution or autogenesis, is the hypothesis that life has an innate tendency to evolve in a unilinear fashion due to some internal or external "driving force". The hypothesis is based on essentialism and cosmic teleology and proposes an intrinsic drive which slowly transforms species. George Gaylord Simpson (1953) in an attack on orthogenesis called this mechanism "the mysterious inner force".[7] Classic proponents of orthogenesis have rejected the theory of natural selection as the organising mechanism in evolution, and theories of speciation for a rectilinear model of guided evolution acting on discrete species with "essences". The term orthogenesis was popularized by Theodor Eimer, though many of the ideas are much older (Bateson 1909).[8]

Def. "the general law according to which evolutionary development takes place in a noticeable direction, above all in specialized groups."[9] is called orthogenesis.

Def. "evolution in a straight line, generally assumed to be evolution that is held to a regular course by forces internal to the organism"[10] is called orthogenesis.

"Orthogenesis assumes that variation is not random but is directed towards fixed goals. Selection is thus powerless, and the species is carried automatically in the direction marked out by internal factors controlling variation."[10]

Darwin himself rarely used the term "evolution" now so commonly used to describe his theory, because in Darwin's time, evolution usually was associated with some sort of progressive process like orthogenesis, and this had been common usage since at least 1647.[11]

Species

[edit | edit source]

"6. The decadent phylum may present as unstable saltations, generic or even higher characters of allied dominant groups; that is a character of generic or even family value in a dominant group may be merely an individual variation in a decadent one. 7. The members of a dominant group are, ceteris paribus, more closely adapted to their environment, their characters less variable, their geographical distribution more restricted. […] 14. Fertility depends chiefly upon the inheritance of physiological characters. A modification in the behavior of the sperm and germ cells may affect fertility even before structural characters have become much affected, and vice versa. Human males and females, as we all know, are sometimes infertile with each other; an extension of this infertility to races would produce what the taxonomist would accept as species. I furthermore believe that the accumulated inheritance of physiological characters may and does produce determinate lines of evolution, that is, orthogenesis, which may go on into hypergenesis, if I may use this term to indicate that hereditary momentum which results in over-development of organs. I account for this accumulated heredity by the action of past environment upon the organism, that is, Lamarckism. I am also quite aware that I am with the minority in the acceptance of Lamarckism as the chief causative principle of the origin of species. I am told that the direct effect of environment in modifying germ characters can not be proven, and I retort, neither can it be disproven. Paleontologists almost universally, and taxonomists generally, are Lamarckians, that is, those who deal chiefly with range and distribution, time and space; laboratory biologists, on the other hand, are almost invariably opposed to the theory of the transmissibility of acquired characters."[12]

Cultures

[edit | edit source]

"For one thing our newer style of evolution is Lamarckian in nature. The environment cannot imprint genetical information upon us, but it can and does imprint non genetical information which we can and do pass on." (Medawar, 1960)

"Whenever biologists and social researchers compare and contrast biological and cultural evolution, almost unanimous agreement is reached on one point – no matter what one may say about evolving culture, it is a 'Lamarckian' process, not a 'Darwinian' one. By this they do not mean that culture is a source of genetic novelty or that culture is determined by genes2 but rather that, considered as a distinct domain of historical process, culture – including social structure, economic systems, ideological and conceptual schemes, and technological and behavioural change – behaves in ways that are analogous to how Lamarckian evolution would operate in biology rather than to how Darwinian evolution does operate. A good many authors use this disparity to argue that, in fact, 'evolution' is not the appropriate word and model for cultural change at all.3"[13]

Recent history

[edit | edit source]

The recent history period dates from around 1,000 b2k to present.

Between 1794 and 1796 Erasmus Darwin wrote Zoonomia suggesting "that all warm-blooded animals have arisen from one living filament with the power of acquiring new parts" in response to stimuli, with each round of "improvements" being inherited by successive generations. Subsequently Jean-Baptiste Lamarck repeated in his Philosophie Zoologique of 1809 the folk wisdom that characteristics which were "needed" were acquired (or diminished) during the lifetime of an organism then passed on to the offspring. He incorporated this mechanism into his thoughts on evolution, seeing it as resulting in the adaptation of life to local environments.

Lamarck stated the following two laws:

  1. Première Loi. Dans tout animal qui n' a point dépassé le terme de ses développemens, l' emploi plus fréquent et soutenu d' un organe quelconque, fortifie peu à peu cet organe, le développe, l' agrandit, et lui donne une puissance proportionnée à la durée de cet emploi ; tandis que le défaut constant d' usage de tel organe, l'affoiblit insensiblement, le détériore, diminue progressivement ses facultés, et finit par le faire disparoître.
  2. Deuxième Loi. Tout ce que la nature a fait acquérir ou perdre aux individus par l' influence des circonstances où leur race se trouve depuis long-temps exposée, et, par conséquent, par l' influence de l' emploi prédominant de tel organe, ou par celle d' un défaut constant d' usage de telle partie ; elle le conserve par la génération aux nouveaux individus qui en proviennent, pourvu que les changemens acquis soient communs aux deux sexes, ou à ceux qui ont produit ces nouveaux individus.[14]
  1. First Law. In every animal which has not exceeded the term of its development, the more frequent and sustained use of any organ strengthens this organ little by little, develops it, enlarges it, and gives it a power proportionate to the duration of this job; while the constant defect of use of such an organ, weakens it imperceptibly, deteriorates it, gradually diminishes its faculties, and finally makes it disappear.
  2. Second Law. All that nature has caused individuals to acquire or lose by the influence of the circumstances in which their race has long been exposed, and, consequently, by the influence of the predominant use of such an organ, or by the influence of a constant lack of use of such part; it preserves it by generation to the new individuals who come from it, provided that the acquired changes are common to both sexes, or to those who have produced these new individuals.

Hypotheses

[edit | edit source]
  1. Lamarckism affects, or refers to effects, on the epigenome.

See also

[edit | edit source]

References

[edit | edit source]
  1. Lamarckism. San Francisco, California: Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. September 17, 2011. http://en.wiktionary.org/wiki/Lamarckism. Retrieved 2012-10-15. 
  2. 2.0 2.1 Stephen Jay Gould (September 15, 2012). Stephen Jay Gould. San Francisco, California: Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. http://en.wikiquote.org/wiki/Stephen_Jay_Gould. Retrieved 2012-10-15. 
  3. Eva Jablonka and Marion J. Lamb (December 2002). "The Changing Concepts of Epigenetics". Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 981: 82-96. doi:10.1111/j.1749-6632.2002.tb04913.x. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1749-6632.2002.tb04913.x/abstract;jsessionid=693F0EA6171DECA75BFFC01763D1A4A6.d04t04?userIsAuthenticated=false&deniedAccessCustomisedMessage=. Retrieved 2012-04-10. 
  4. 4.0 4.1 4.2 4.3 Evolutionary Biology/Jean-Baptiste Lamarck. San Francisco, California: Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. 15 October 2012. http://en.wikibooks.org/wiki/Evolutionary_Biology/Jean-Baptiste_Lamarck. Retrieved 2012-10-15. 
  5. Lamarck (April 14, 2012). On Modification and Variation. San Francisco, California: Wikimedia Foundation, Inc. http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/On_Modification_and_Variation. Retrieved 2012-10-15. 
  6. Gene Wolfe (1982). Sun of Helioscope, In: Castle of the Otter. 
  7. George Gaylord Simpson, Life of the Past: An Introduction to Paleontology, Yale University Press, New Haven, 1953, p. 125.
  8. The evolutionary future of man: A biological view of progress
  9. The phenomenon of Teilhard: prophet for a new age, David H. Lane, 1996, p. 61
  10. 10.0 10.1 Evolution: the history of an idea, Peter J. Bowler, 1989, p. 268
  11. Darwin's Dilemma: The Odyssey of Evolution, Stephen Jay Gould, an essay in Ever Since Darwin: Reflections in Natural History, W. W. Norton, 1977, ISBN 0-393-06425-5
  12. S. W. Willistion (March 1908). "What is a Species?". The American Naturalist 42 (495): 184-94. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2455679?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents. Retrieved 2015-07-09. 
  13. John S. Wilkins (31 May 2001). John Nightingale and John Laurent. ed. The Appearance of Lamarckism in the Evolution of Culture, In: Darwinism and evolutionary economics. Edward Elgar Publisher. pp. 160-183. ISBN 978-1840642094. https://www.researchgate.net/profile/John_Wilkins4/publication/43471850_The_appearance_of_Lamarckism_in_the_evolution_of_culture/links/0f317530eb6abcf535000000.pdf. Retrieved 24 July 2019. 
  14. Jean-Baptiste Lamarck Philosophie zoologique ch.7, p.235

Further reading

[edit | edit source]
[edit | edit source]

{{History of science resources}}